Author: | Anton Trunov |
---|---|
Date: | April 8, 2021 |
Set Implicit Arguments. Unset Strict Implicit. Unset Printing Implicit Defensive.
During the first part of the course we saw how to build proof terms by hand. It turns out it is quite tedious to do that for less trivial developments than the examples we have. There is a number of meta-languages called tactic languages to help us build (proof) terms. Tactic languages provide a user interface allowing us to perform proof steps resembling logical rules of inference more than functional programming we did so far. But in the end tactic languages produce proof terms and that is it, there is no magic it, except that tactic languages can automate some mundane steps making the overall process of proving more pleasant.
Let's see some concrete examples and learn one such tactic language, called SSReflect. We are going to learn SSReflect by example, so you'd like a more formal approach then I can refer you to the reference manual: https://coq.github.io/doc/master/refman/proof-engine/ssreflect-proof-language.html.
Here is an example of using the SSReflct tactic language to prove a simple lemma:
forall A : Prop, A -> Aforall A : Prop, A -> AA:PropA -> Aexact: proof_A. Qed.A:Propproof_A:AA
Let's break the example above down.
Lemma A_implies_A : forall (A : Prop), A -> A.
The type forall (A : Prop), A -> A
is the
statement of a lemma named A_implies_A
. The
Lemma
vernacular essentially means Definition
.
But in this case, instead of providing the body of
the definition after the :=
syntax we finish the
statement with a dot (.
).
So, after that dot Coq switches us into its proof mode where it shows us our current proof goal in a window (or in a terminal) and waits for our input.
After the lemma statement it is customary to put
an optional Proof
vernacular which does nothing
semantically but it suggests we are going to start
a new proof.
move=> A. move=> proof_A. exact: proof_A.
This piece of code is an example of using
tactics to build a proof term. The tactics between
between Proof
and Qed
are commonly referred to
as "proof". But from the theoretical point of view
it is, of course, not a proof but a recipe to
build a proof. Each tactic invocation build the
underlying proof term incrementally. And since
SSReflect proof scripts alone (without using
interactive theorem proving) don't show you the
intermediate proofs steps, people often say it has
imperative flavor to it: you see some commands to
change the known part of the proof term but not
the term itsel. We are going to manually
instrument the proof to see how the underlying
term gets build incrementally.
The first tactic call move=> A
means "assume A
is an arbitrary proposition". The move=> proof_A
incantation means "assume we have A
as our
assumption". Having all that we can finish our
proof by providing the exact solution with exact:
proof_A
.
The proof is finished with the Qed
vernacular
which triggers re-typechecking of the proof term
and also seals the proof, i.e. it makes the body
of the lemma definition opaque which helps with
speeding up typechecking because the typechecker
does not need to unfold the body of the lemma
since it is computationally irrelevant and all we
care about is that we have a name and its type
now. One can check if a given definition is
transparent or opaque using the About
vernacular.
To understand better what is going on here, first
of all, let us note that the proof goal forall (A
: Prop), A -> A
can be seen as a stack of
variables and assumtions, where the top of the
stack in our case is the variable A
, the next
stack element is an assumption that we have a
proof of A
and the last stack element is called
conclusion, which is again A
in our case.
The double arrow (=>
) is a tactical, it takes
a tactic (to its left) and a list of "actions",
tac=> act1 act2 ... act_n
. First, Coq applies
the tactic tac
to the top of the goal stack, And
then it executes actions from left to right. If an
action happens to be an identifier then it gets
introduced to the proof context which keeps the
knowledge available to us w.r.t. the current
proof. The proof context is visually represented
as the area located just above the bar (=======
)
in the "goals" response from Coq.
The move
tactic is like a no-operation tactic we
put mostly because =>
needs a tactic to the left
of itself.
(Note: actually move
can convert the goal to the
head normal form, but let us ignore this for now.)
The exact
tactic tells Coq the exact solution of
the current subgoal. (I'm actually cheating right
now because :
is a tactical as well and I'd like
to postpone its discussion a bit).
Now let's run the intrumented version and see
what is going on under the hood. We are going to
use the Show Proof
vernacular command to display
the current (incomplete) proof term. Identifiers
prefixed with question marks stand for proof
"holes", i.e. some yet to be defined term. For
instance, ?Goal
stands for the current proof
goal Coq displays.
forall A : Prop, A -> Aforall A : Prop, A -> AA:PropA -> AA:PropA -> AA:Propproof_A:AAexact: proof_A.A:Propproof_A:AAUnset Printing Notations.Set Printing Notations. Qed.
Let's see some more proofs and some new tactics and tacticals. By the way, we have already done the following proofs earlier by providing explicit proof terms.
A, B:PropA -> B -> AA, B:PropA -> B -> AA, B:Propa:AB -> Aexact: a. Qed.A, B:Propa:AA
Let's introduce the apply
tactic which
applies the top of the goal stack to the
conclusion and might ask the user to prove an
assumption needed to do this. This tactic
facilitates the so-called backward reasoning: we
start with the goals conclusion and work our way
up by proving assumtions needed to finish the
proof.
A, B:PropA -> (A -> B) -> BA, B:PropA -> (A -> B) -> BA, B:Propa:A(A -> B) -> Bexact: a. Qed.A, B:Propa:AA
To take apart terms of inductive types, i.e.
to use the tactic-level analogue of pattern
matching, one can use the case
tactic.
The case
tactic, as many SSReflect tactics,
applies to the top of the goal stack, and
translates into pattern-matching at the term
level. E.g. if the top of the goal stack is a
conjunction then the top gets removed and two new
conjuncts get pushed on the goal stack. If the top
of the goal stack is a disjunction then the top of
the stack gets consumed and Coq generates two
subgoals corresponding to the left and right
disjuncts.
Let us see how to apply it to a conjunctive hypothesis.
In the proof below we could use two tactis move=>
a. move=> b.
to move two assumptions into the
proof context but it's easier to combined the two
commands into just one move=> a b.
. And, by the
way, if you don't need an assumption then you can
use an underscore (_
) after the double arrow to
clean it from the goal stack.
A, B:PropA /\ B -> AA, B:PropA /\ B -> AA, B:PropA -> B -> Aexact: a. Qed.A, B:Propa:AA
On the other hand, to prove conjunctive goals
one needs the split
tactic which allows one to
prove the two conjuncts as separate subgoals.
A, B:PropA /\ B -> B /\ AA, B:PropA /\ B -> B /\ AA, B:PropA -> B -> B /\ A(* prove conjunction: creates one more subgoal *)A, B:Propa:Ab:BB /\ A(* 1st subgoal marked with a bullet and indented *)A, B:Propa:Ab:BBA, B:Propa:Ab:BAA, B:Propa:Ab:BBA, B:Propa:Ab:BAexact: a. Qed.A, B:Propa:Ab:BA
Now, let's see how to use case
for
disjunctive assumptions and also how to use the
left
and right
tactics to prove disjunctive
goals.
The left
tactic tells Coq that we are going to
prove the disjunctive goal at hand by proving the
left disjunct. The right
tactics does the same
but for the right disjunct.
A, B:PropA \/ B -> B \/ AA, B:PropA \/ B -> B \/ AA, B:PropA -> B \/ AA, B:PropB -> B \/ AA, B:PropA -> B \/ AA, B:PropB -> B \/ AA, B:Propa:AB \/ AA, B:PropB -> B \/ AA, B:Propa:AAA, B:PropB -> B \/ AA, B:PropB -> B \/ AA, B:Propb:BB \/ Aexact: b. Qed.A, B:Propb:BB
Let's put to work all the above together and prove a lemma with a bit more involved proof.
A, B, C:Prop(A \/ B) /\ C -> A /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:Prop(A \/ B) /\ C -> A /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:PropA \/ B -> C -> A /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:PropA -> C -> A /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:PropB -> C -> A /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:PropA -> C -> A /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:PropB -> C -> A /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:Propa:Ac:CA /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:PropB -> C -> A /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:Propa:Ac:CA /\ CA, B, C:PropB -> C -> A /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:Propa:Ac:CAA, B, C:Propa:Ac:CCA, B, C:PropB -> C -> A /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:Propa:Ac:CAA, B, C:Propa:Ac:CCA, B, C:PropB -> C -> A /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:Propa:Ac:CCA, B, C:PropB -> C -> A /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:PropB -> C -> A /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:Propb:Bc:CA /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:Propb:Bc:CB /\ CA, B, C:Propb:Bc:CBA, B, C:Propb:Bc:CCA, B, C:Propb:Bc:CBA, B, C:Propb:Bc:CCexact: c. Qed.A, B, C:Propb:Bc:CC
The lemma statement above can be considered as trivial by experienced proof engineers, so more than 10 LoC proof looks a bit large for a trivial statement. And, indeed, we can make it much more concise. Let us try it again on the same lemma.
A, B, C:Prop(A \/ B) /\ C -> A /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:Prop(A \/ B) /\ C -> A /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:PropA \/ B -> C -> A /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:Propa:Ac:CA /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:Propb:Bc:CA /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:Propa:Ac:CA /\ C \/ B /\ CA, B, C:Propb:Bc:CA /\ C \/ B /\ Cby right. Qed.A, B, C:Propb:Bc:CA /\ C \/ B /\ C
We have used several important features of the SSReflect proof language:
- intro-patterns, and
- [by] tactical.
Remember that the =>
tactical can be
prepended by a number of tactics (but not all of
them), including the case
tactic. In the example
above we split the conjunctive assumption first
and then case analyse on the disjunction using the
case=> [act1 | act2 | ...]
syntax to perform
some actions on the top of the goal stack in each
generated subgoal. In our case
case=> [a|b].
sort of means
case. - move=> a. (* 1st active subgoal *) move=> b. (* 2nd active subgoal *)
but we still have both subgoals to process.
The [act1 | act2 | ...] syntax is an instance of intro-patterns.
The by
tactical takes a list of tactics (or
a single tactic), applies it to the goal and then
tries to finish the proof using some simple proof
automation. E.g. by []
means "the proof of the
goal is trivial", because Coq does not need any
hints from the user. This is equivalent to using
the done
tactic. And, for instance, the by
left
tactic means "we are going to the left
conjunct but it's proof is trivial". The local
proof automation we use here is sufficiently smart
to split conjunctive goals into several subgoals
but it won't try more advanced forms of proof
search like trying to prove the left disjunct and
if it does not work out then backtrack and try
proving the right disjunct.
The by
, exact
and done
tactics/tacticals are
called terminators because if these do not solve
the goal completely, the user gets an error
message and the goal state gets restored. It is
recommended to put the terminators to mark where
the current subgoal is proven completely. This
helps fixing proofs when they break due to, for
instance, changes in the definitions of the
project.
An even terser version of the proof of our
current example can be written using one more
instance of intro-patterns: [act1 act2 ...]
which is used to break a conjunction-like
assumption and execute each of the actions on each
component, as in [[a|b] c]
below.
One can also use the semicolon (;
) tactical:
tac1; tac2
means "execute the tac1
tactic and
then execute the tac2
tactic on each of the
generated by tac1
subgoals". This can be
extended to tac; [tac1 | tac2 | ...]
which means
"execute tac
and then execute tac
\(_i\) on
the \(i\)-th subgoal".
If there is a mismatch between the number of
subgoals and the number of supplied tactics you'll
see an error message. The user is allowed to skip
some tactics (or all of them), but the
corresponding pipe (|
) symbols must be provided,
i.e. tac; [| tac2 |]
gets executed like so:
first tac
gets applied to the goal and generates
3 subgoals, then tac2
gets applied to the second
subgoal.
Here is the resulting one-line proof we get after combining the features we discussed so far.
A, B, C:Prop(A \/ B) /\ C -> A /\ C \/ B /\ Cby case=> [[a|b] c]; [left | right]. Qed.A, B, C:Prop(A \/ B) /\ C -> A /\ C \/ B /\ C
There is one missing puzzle piece for us: we can introduce hypotheses to the proof context but cannot move them back to the top of the goal stack and this is something that we need frequently when proving lemmas in SSReflect.
The colon (:
) tactical solves precisely this
problem: move: foo
in a sense is a reversal of
move=> foo
.
Let's illustrate the usage of the colon tactical with the following example.
A, B, C:Type(A -> B -> C) -> (A -> B) -> A -> CA, B, C:Type(A -> B -> C) -> (A -> B) -> A -> CA, B, C:Typeabc:A -> B -> Cab:A -> Ba:ACA, B, C:Typeab:A -> Ba:A(A -> B -> C) -> CA, B, C:Typeab:A -> Ba:AAA, B, C:Typeab:A -> Ba:ABA, B, C:Typeab:A -> Ba:AAA, B, C:Typeab:A -> Ba:ABA, B, C:Typeab:A -> Ba:ABA, B, C:Typea:A(A -> B) -> Bdone. Qed.A, B, C:Typea:AA
Since :
is a tactical we can combine it not
only with move
but other tactics as well, for
example, with the apply
tactic. The invocation
apply: foo
can be read as "apply the lemma (or
hypothesis) foo
" to the goal. But actually what
we do here is we move foo
to the top of the goal
stack and apply it to the rest of the goal stack.
Moving a hypothesis back to the goal stack makes
it disappear from the proof context. If you need
to apply a hypothesis to the goal and still keep
it in the context, use parentheses around the
hypothesis name: apply: (foo)
.
We can simplify the proof of the lemma above as follows.
A, B, C:Type(A -> B -> C) -> (A -> B) -> A -> CA, B, C:Type(A -> B -> C) -> (A -> B) -> A -> CA, B, C:Typeabc:A -> B -> Cab:A -> Ba:ACA, B, C:Typeab:A -> Ba:AAA, B, C:Typeab:A -> Ba:ABA, B, C:Typeab:A -> Ba:AAA, B, C:Typeab:A -> Ba:ABby apply: ab. Qed.A, B, C:Typeab:A -> Ba:AB
Notice that the proof above contains a
trivially provable subgoal? To handle cases like
this one there is a special action //
meaning
"try solving the new trivial subgoal and do not
change a subgoal if it's not trivial". This action
can be integrated into a tactic call using the
double arrow tactical, see the example below.
A, B, C:Type(A -> B -> C) -> (A -> B) -> A -> CA, B, C:Type(A -> B -> C) -> (A -> B) -> A -> CA, B, C:Typeabc:A -> B -> Cab:A -> Ba:ACby apply: ab. Qed.A, B, C:Typeab:A -> Ba:AB
rewrite
tactic and ->
actionThe rewrite
tactic lets us use equations. If
eq : x = y
then rewrite eq
changes x
's in
the goal to y
's. And rewrite -eq
does
rewriting in the opposite direction.
Section RewriteTactic. Variable A : Type. Implicit Types x y z : A.A:Typex, y:Ax = y -> y = xA:Typex, y:Ax = y -> y = xA:Typex, y:Ax_eq_y:x = yy = xby []. Qed.A:Typex, y:Ax_eq_y:x = yy = y
move=> eq; rewrite eq
is a frequent pattern
so there is an abbreviation for it introduced as
an action ->
which can be combined with the =>
tactical.
This action uses the top of the goal stack (which
must be an equation) and does rewriting. There is
also the symmetrical <-
action.
A:Typex, y:Ax = y -> y = xA:Typex, y:Ax = y -> y = xdone. Qed.A:Typex, y:Ay = yA:Typex, y, z:Ax = y -> y = z -> x = zA:Typex, y, z:Ax = y -> y = z -> x = zdone. Qed. End RewriteTactic.A:Typex, y, z:Ay = z -> y = z
associative addnassociative addnforall x y z : nat, x + (y + z) = x + y + z(* But the above solution if not idiomatic, the experienced user knows what `associative` looks like, and the `=>` tactical can look inside of definitions *)x, y, z:natx + (y + z) = x + y + zassociative addnassociative addn(* Proving this lemma needs induction which we can ask Coq to use with `elim` tactic. We'd like to do induction on the variable `x`. But, as usual, `elim` operates on the top of the goal stack, so we need to put back `x` into the goal: *)x, y, z:natx + (y + z) = x + y + zy, z:natforall x : nat, x + (y + z) = x + y + zy, z:nat0 + (y + z) = 0 + y + zy, z:natforall n : nat, n + (y + z) = n + y + z -> n.+1 + (y + z) = n.+1 + y + zy, z:nat0 + (y + z) = 0 + y + zy, z:natforall n : nat, n + (y + z) = n + y + z -> n.+1 + (y + z) = n.+1 + y + z(* Notice that `elim` uses the `nat_ind` induction principle under the hood. *)y, z:nat0 + (y + z) = 0 + y + zy, z:natforall n : nat, n + (y + z) = n + y + z -> n.+1 + (y + z) = n.+1 + y + z(* `0 + (y + z)` reduces into `y + z` and `0 + y` reduces to `y`, hence the goal is equivalent to `y + z = y + z`, i.e. it can be solved trivially. *)y, z:nat0 + (y + z) = 0 + y + zy, z:natforall n : nat, n + (y + z) = n + y + z -> n.+1 + (y + z) = n.+1 + y + z(* inductive step *) (* [IH] stands for "induction hypothesis" *)y, z:natforall n : nat, n + (y + z) = n + y + z -> n.+1 + (y + z) = n.+1 + y + zy, z, x:natIHx:x + (y + z) = x + y + zx.+1 + (y + z) = x.+1 + y + z(* To use `IHx` we need to change the goal to contain `x + (y + z)`. To achieve this we need to use a lemma which lets us simplify `x.+1 + y` into `(x + y).+1`. Let's use the `Search` mechanism to find such a lemma: *)y, z, x:natIHx:x + (y + z) = x + y + zx.+1 + (y + z) = x.+1 + y + z(* This query returns a list of lemmas and a brief examination shows `addSn` is the lemma we are looking for *)y, z, x:natIHx:x + (y + z) = x + y + zx.+1 + (y + z) = x.+1 + y + z(* Now we can use the induction hypothesis *)y, z, x:natIHx:x + (y + z) = x + y + z(x + (y + z)).+1 = x.+1 + y + zdone.y, z, x:natIHx:x + (y + z) = x + y + z(x + y + z).+1 = x.+1 + y + z(* The proof can be simplified into: *) by move=> x y z; elim: x=> // x IHx; rewrite addSn IHx. Qed.associative addn
See this great cheatsheet on SSReflect tactic, notations and even more things.
=>
: the (simplified)
grammar is tac=> act
and it means "perform the
tactic tac
and then do the action act
". If
act
is an identifier ident
, then it is
interpreted as "move the top of the goal stack
to the proof context and give it a name
ident
".move
tactic: think of it as a placeholder for
tacticals for now. For instance, =>
needs a
tactic to the left of it, so if you don't need
to call any tactic, just use move
.exact
tactic: works like by apply
.apply
tactic applies the top of the goal stack
to the conclusion and might ask the user to prove
an assumption needed to do this. This tactic
facilitates the so-called backward reasoning.case
tactic translates to pattern matching
and can be used to destruct conjunctions into
proof components or do proof by case analysis
for disjunctive assumptions.split
tactic lets us prove conjunctive goals
by proving its components as separate subgoals.left
tactic to prove left disjuncts.right
tactic to prove right disjuncts.
- identifier: refers to the top of the goal stack or a hypothesis in the context.
[act1 act2 ...]
: destruct conjunction-like assumptions.[act1 | act2 | ...]
: case analysis.->
: rewrite in the goal with the top of the goal stack (from left to right).<-
: rewrite in the goal with the top of the goal stack (from right to left).
Lemma
: think of it as a synonym for Definition
.Proof
: an optional command which marks the
beginning of a proof.Qed
: a vernacular which finishes a proof and
makes the lemma body opaque.Show Proof
: a vernacular which displays the
current (possibly unfinished) proof term.Section
: groups several related definitions
and/or theorems together and lets the user
define common variables / hypotheses for the
section definitions.Variable
: declare a section variable which is
going to be abstracted over at the end of the
current section.Implicit Types
: declare the types of section
variables to reduce boilerplate and make
typechecking faster in some cases.Restart
: restart the current proof.Show
: display the current proof goal.