Built with Alectryon, running Coq+SerAPI v8.13.0+0.13.0. Bubbles () indicate interactive fragments: hover for details, tap to reveal contents. Use Ctrl+↑ Ctrl+↓ to navigate, Ctrl+🖱️ to focus. On Mac, use instead of Ctrl.

Views. reflect-predicate. Multi-rewrite rules

Author: Anton Trunov
Date: April 22, 2021
Notation "[ rel _ _ | _ ]" was already used in scope fun_scope. [notation-overridden,parsing]
Notation "[ rel _ _ : _ | _ ]" was already used in scope fun_scope. [notation-overridden,parsing]
Notation "[ rel _ _ in _ & _ | _ ]" was already used in scope fun_scope. [notation-overridden,parsing]
Notation "[ rel _ _ in _ & _ ]" was already used in scope fun_scope. [notation-overridden,parsing]
Notation "[ rel _ _ in _ | _ ]" was already used in scope fun_scope. [notation-overridden,parsing]
Notation "[ rel _ _ in _ ]" was already used in scope fun_scope. [notation-overridden,parsing]
Notation "_ + _" was already used in scope nat_scope. [notation-overridden,parsing]
Notation "_ - _" was already used in scope nat_scope. [notation-overridden,parsing]
Notation "_ <= _" was already used in scope nat_scope. [notation-overridden,parsing]
Notation "_ < _" was already used in scope nat_scope. [notation-overridden,parsing]
Notation "_ >= _" was already used in scope nat_scope. [notation-overridden,parsing]
Notation "_ > _" was already used in scope nat_scope. [notation-overridden,parsing]
Notation "_ <= _ <= _" was already used in scope nat_scope. [notation-overridden,parsing]
Notation "_ < _ <= _" was already used in scope nat_scope. [notation-overridden,parsing]
Notation "_ <= _ < _" was already used in scope nat_scope. [notation-overridden,parsing]
Notation "_ < _ < _" was already used in scope nat_scope. [notation-overridden,parsing]
Notation "_ * _" was already used in scope nat_scope. [notation-overridden,parsing]
Set Implicit Arguments. Unset Strict Implicit. Unset Printing Implicit Defensive.

reflect-predicate

As we mentioned earlier, the SSReflect proof methodology is based on having logical and symbolic (e.g. boolean) representations intermixed in a goal, so that the user can switch between those to drive the proof process.

The SSReflect methodology, thus, favors computable predicates and relations.

Let's see an example now.

Motivational example

T:Type
p:pred T
s:seq T

all p s -> [seq x <- s | p x] = s
T:Type
p:pred T
s:seq T

all p s -> [seq x <- s | p x] = s

First of all, let's try and understand the goal we see here. There are several things:

  • p : pred T means p is a computable predicate over type T, i.e. pred T is T -> bool;
  • all p s means all elements of sequence s satisfy predicate p;
  • [seq x <- s | p x] notation stands for filter (fun x => p x) s.

We can check all the above bullet points with the following three simple commands:

pred = fun T : Type => T -> bool : Type -> Type Arguments pred _%type_scope
all : pred ?T -> seq ?T -> bool where ?T : [T : Type p : pred T s : seq T |- Type]
Notation "[ 'seq' x <- s | C ]" := (filter (fun x => C) s) : seq_scope (default interpretation)

But wait a minute, how come we can have a term of type bool as an assumption in our goal?

all p s : bool : bool
T:Type
p:pred T
s:seq T

all p s -> [seq x <- s | p x] = s

And why the following works at all?

all p s : Type : Type
T:Type
p:pred T
s:seq T

all p s -> [seq x <- s | p x] = s

This works because of the mechanism of implicit coercions Coq uses to make sense of goals like the current one. To see clearly what is going on here, use the following vernacular:

T:Type
p:pred T
s:seq T

is_true (all p s) -> [seq x <- s | p x] = s

Now we can see Coq inserted the corcion is_true around all p s so the goal would actually make sense.

is_true = eq^~ true : bool -> Prop Arguments is_true _%bool_scope is_true is a coercion

If eq^~ true does not really make sense for you:

Notation "f ^~ y" := (fun x => f x y) : fun_scope (default interpretation)

Another approach would be to unfold is_true:

T:Type
p:pred T
s:seq T

all p s = true -> [seq x <- s | p x] = s

Given the above, is_true b means b = true -- this is one way to embed booleans into Prop.

T:Type
p:pred T
s:seq T

all p s = true -> [seq x <- s | p x] = s

Now that we understand the goal we can prove it by induction on s:

T:Type
p:pred T
x:T
s:seq T
IHs:all p s = true -> [seq x <- s | p x] = s

p x && all p s = true -> (if p x then x :: [seq x <- s | p x] else [seq x <- s | p x]) = x :: s

In our top assumption we have both p x which is needed to simplify the if-expression in the goal conclusion and all p s which is needed to apply the induction hypothesis. So, at this point we need to transform an assumption from its symbolic form ?x && ?y = true into its logical form ?x = true /\ ?y = true.

To do this we are going to use the mechanism of views supported by SSReflect.

T:Type
p:pred T
x:T
s:seq T
IHs:all p s = true -> [seq x <- s | p x] = s

p x /\ all p s -> (if p x then x :: [seq x <- s | p x] else [seq x <- s | p x]) = x :: s

We already know the /lemma syntax as we saw how it works for lemmas which are implications. In this case it's something like this as well, although there is some implicit machinery at work too. The mechanism is called view hints and we are going to cover it later. The rest of the proof is very straightforward.

T:Type
p:pred T
x:T
s:seq T
IHs:all p s = true -> [seq x <- s | p x] = s

p x -> all p s -> (if p x then x :: [seq x <- s | p x] else [seq x <- s | p x]) = x :: s
T:Type
p:pred T
x:T
s:seq T
IHs:all p s = true -> [seq x <- s | p x] = s

all p s -> x :: [seq x <- s | p x] = x :: s
T:Type
p:pred T
x:T
s:seq T
IHs:all p s = true -> [seq x <- s | p x] = s

[seq x <- s | p x] = s -> x :: [seq x <- s | p x] = x :: s
T:Type
p:pred T
x:T
s:seq T
IHs:all p s = true -> [seq x <- s | p x] = s

x :: s = x :: s
done.

Let us refactor the proof above into something more idiomatic

T:Type
p:pred T
s:seq T

all p s -> [seq x <- s | p x] = s
by elim: s=> //= x s IHs /andP[-> /IHs->]. Qed.

reflect-predicate: definition

So, what is reflect in the type of andP from above?

andP : forall {b1 b2 : bool}, reflect (b1 /\ b2) (b1 && b2) andP is not universe polymorphic Arguments andP {b1 b2}%bool_scope andP is opaque Expands to: Constant Coq.ssr.ssrbool.andP
Notation reflect := Bool.reflect
Inductive reflect (P : Prop) : bool -> Set := ReflectT : P -> reflect P true | ReflectF : ~ P -> reflect P false Arguments Bool.reflect _%type_scope _%bool_scope Arguments Bool.ReflectT _%type_scope _ Arguments Bool.ReflectF _%type_scope _

The reflect type family (or indexed type, in other words) connects a decidable proposition to the corresponding boolean expression. This is not the first time we come across an indexed type but it's the first time we run into an indexed type with two constructors where we can clearly see the difference between parameters (which have to be fixed across constructors, P here is a parameter) and indices (which can vary between constructors). In this case, type-level boolean term indicates which constructor has been used to construct a term of type reflect P b, e.g. when one has a term of type reflect P true they know the ReflectT constructor has been used to construct the term which means we have a proof of P we can get by pattern-matching on a term of type reflect P true. (And pattern-matching on a term of type reflect P false yields a refutation of P.)


forall P : Prop, reflect P true -> P
P:Prop

reflect P true -> P
exact: ( fun r : reflect P true => match r in reflect _ b return (b = true -> P) with | ReflectT p => fun E => p | ReflectF np => fun E => ltac:(done) end erefl).
P:Prop

reflect P true -> P
P:Prop

P -> P
P:Prop
~ P -> P

case actually leads to unprovable goals here. It's not intelligent enough to solve this goal which requires dependent pattern matching. We need to use a special version of case for type families. Here is the syntax we need to solve this.

P:Prop

reflect P true -> P
P:Prop
R:reflect P true

P
P:Prop
_p_:P
E:true = true

P
P:Prop
_n_:~ P
E:true = false
P

To the right of / we put a term (R in this case) we are going to case analyse -- this needs to be a type family. And to the left of / we put the indices of the type family we'd like to get substituted. Notice that we need to keep the relation between the original value of the index true and its values inside the branches of the underlying match-expression and this is what E in case: E is for.

P:Prop
_p_:P
E:true = true

P
P:Prop
_n_:~ P
E:true = false
P
P:Prop
_n_:~ P
E:true = false

P
done.

forall P : Prop, reflect P true -> P

Instead of move=> R; case E: true / R we can use a shorhand:

by move=> P; case E: true /.


forall P : Prop, reflect P true -> P

Moreover, SSReflect can figure out the indices on its own:

by move=> P; case E: _/.
Qed.

A lemma like reflect P false -> ~ P can be proved analogously.

To reinforce what has been said already, let us formally prove several lemmas about reflect. For instance, we can show P if and only if b = true as two separate lemmas.

P:Prop
b:bool

reflect P b -> P -> b
P:Prop
b:bool

reflect P b -> P -> b
P:Prop
b:bool

P -> P -> true
P:Prop
b:bool
~ P -> P -> false

The index b here works as a rewrite rule.

P:Prop
b:bool

P -> P -> true
P:Prop
b:bool
~ P -> P -> false
P:Prop
b:bool

~ P -> P -> false
by move=> /[apply]. Qed.

The other direction is left as an exercise for the reader.

P:Prop
b:bool

reflect P b -> b -> P
Admitted.

Essentially, we have shown reflect P b -> (b <-> P), i.e. reflect P b connects a decidable proposition P to its decision procedure (the boolean expression b).

For example, we can show reflect P b lets us use classical reasoning (exercise):

P:Prop
b:bool

reflect P b -> P \/ ~ P
Admitted.

Lets look at how to build reflect-predicates for a couple of standard connectives.

b, c:bool

reflect (b /\ c) (b && c)
b, c:bool

reflect (b /\ c) (b && c)
c:bool

reflect (true /\ c) (true && c)
c:bool
reflect (false /\ c) (false && c)
c:bool

reflect (true /\ c) (true && c)
c:bool
reflect (false /\ c) (false && c)

reflect (true /\ true) (true && true)

reflect (true /\ false) (true && false)
c:bool
reflect (false /\ c) (false && c)

reflect (true /\ true) (true && true)

reflect (true /\ false) (true && false)
c:bool
reflect (false /\ c) (false && c)

true /\ true

reflect (true /\ false) (true && false)
c:bool
reflect (false /\ c) (false && c)

reflect (true /\ false) (true && false)
c:bool
reflect (false /\ c) (false && c)

reflect (true /\ false) (true && false)
c:bool
reflect (false /\ c) (false && c)

~ (true /\ false)
c:bool
reflect (false /\ c) (false && c)
c:bool

reflect (false /\ c) (false && c)
c:bool

reflect (false /\ c) (false && c)
c:bool

~ (false /\ c)
b, c:bool

reflect (b /\ c) (b && c)

An idiomatic solution would look something like so:

by case: b; case: c; constructor=> //; case.
Qed.

b, c:bool

reflect (~~ b \/ ~~ c) (~~ (b && c))
b, c:bool

reflect (~~ b \/ ~~ c) (~~ (b && c))

~ (~~ true \/ ~~ true)

~~ true \/ ~~ false

~~ false \/ ~~ true

~~ false \/ ~~ false

~ (~~ true \/ ~~ true)

~~ true \/ ~~ false

~~ false \/ ~~ true

~~ false \/ ~~ false

~~ true \/ ~~ false

~~ false \/ ~~ true

~~ false \/ ~~ false

~~ true \/ ~~ false

~~ false \/ ~~ true

~~ false \/ ~~ false

~~ false \/ ~~ true

~~ false \/ ~~ false

~~ false \/ ~~ true

~~ false \/ ~~ false

~~ false \/ ~~ false
by left.
b, c:bool

reflect (~~ b \/ ~~ c) (~~ (b && c))

This seems to be a rare opportunity for an automatic tactic to fill in the blanks for us: the intuition tactic can take care of the subgoals generated by our brute force approach.

by case: b; case: c; constructor; intuition.
Qed.

Sometimes we will need to use reflect b b as a placeholder. This is an easy exercise.

b:bool

reflect b b
Admitted.

Using reflection views on assumptions

Let's continue figuring out how and why andP works.

b, c:bool

b && c -> b /\ c
b, c:bool

b && c -> b /\ c
b, c:bool

b /\ c -> b /\ c
(fun (b c : bool) (_view_subject_ : b && c) => ?Goal (elimTF andP _view_subject_))
b, c:bool

b /\ c -> b /\ c

We see andP in a context of elimTF, let's see what it is.

elimTF : forall [P : Prop] [b c : bool], reflect P b -> b = c -> if c then P else ~ P elimTF is not universe polymorphic Arguments elimTF [P]%type_scope [b c]%bool_scope _ _ elimTF is opaque Expands to: Constant Coq.ssr.ssrbool.elimTF
b, c:bool

b /\ c -> b /\ c

elimTF is a generalization of elimT we proved above.

b, c:bool

b && c -> b /\ c

Let us see what is going on when we say move/andP:

b, c:bool
Hb:b && c

b /\ c
elimTF andP Hb : b /\ c
b, c:bool
Hb:b && c

b /\ c
b, c:bool

b && c -> b /\ c
b, c:bool

b /\ c -> b /\ c

But where elimTF comes from? SSReflect uses the mechanism of view hints which provide some wrapping lemmas such as elimTF above. The user can add a new view hint using the Hint View vernacular Hint View for move/ elimTF|3.

Here elimTF is declared as a view hint for the move/ command. The (optional) number 3 specifies the number of implicit arguments to be considered for the declared hint view lemma.

The ssrbool.v module already declares a numbers of view hints, so adding new ones should be justified. For instance, one might need to do it if one defines a new logical connective.

exact: id.
Qed.

But why is elimTF's type so complex? Because it's applicable not only in the case the goal's top assumtion is of the form b && c, but it also works for b && c = false.

b, c:bool

b && c = false -> ~ (b /\ c)
b, c:bool

b && c = false -> ~ (b /\ c)
b, c:bool

~ (b /\ c) -> ~ (b /\ c)
(fun (b c : bool) (_view_subject_ : b && c = false) => ?Goal (elimTF andP _view_subject_))
b, c:bool

~ (b /\ c) -> ~ (b /\ c)
b, c:bool

b && c = false -> ~ (b /\ c)
b, c:bool
Hb:b && c = false

~ (b /\ c)
elimTF andP Hb : ~ (b /\ c)
b, c:bool
Hb:b && c = false

~ (b /\ c)
exact: @elimTF (b /\ c) (b && c) false (@andP b c) Hb. Qed.

Reflection views usually work in both directions

b, c:bool

b /\ c -> b && c
b, c:bool

b /\ c -> b && c
b, c:bool

b && c -> b && c
(fun (b c : bool) (_view_subject_ : b /\ c) => ?Goal (introT andP _view_subject_))
b, c:bool

b && c -> b && c
introT : forall [P : Prop] [b : bool], reflect P b -> P -> b introT is not universe polymorphic Arguments introT [P]%type_scope [b]%bool_scope _ _ introT is opaque Expands to: Constant Coq.ssr.ssrbool.introT
b, c:bool

b && c -> b && c

introT view hint gets implicitly inserted because it is also declared with Hint View command.

done.
Qed.

Switching views at the goal

b, c:bool

b /\ c -> b && c
b, c:bool

b /\ c -> b && c
b, c:bool
bc:b /\ c

b && c

If we'd like, instead of the assumption, change the goal, we can use apply/ tactic:

b, c:bool
bc:b /\ c

b /\ c
(fun (b c : bool) (bc : b /\ c) => [eta introTF andP] ?Goal)
b, c:bool
bc:b /\ c

b /\ c

In this case the introTF view hint gets inserted because the ssrbool module introduces the correspoding view hint: Hint View for apply/ introTF|3

introTF : forall [P : Prop] [b c : bool], reflect P b -> (if c then P else ~ P) -> b = c introTF is not universe polymorphic Arguments introTF [P]%type_scope [b c]%bool_scope _ _ introTF is opaque Expands to: Constant Coq.ssr.ssrbool.introTF
b, c:bool
bc:b /\ c

b /\ c
done. Qed.

Again, introTF is a general lemma to accomodate goals of the form _ = false.

b, c:bool

~ (b /\ c) -> b && c = false
b, c:bool

~ (b /\ c) -> b && c = false
b, c:bool
ab:~ (b /\ c)

b && c = false
b, c:bool
ab:~ (b /\ c)

~ (b /\ c)
(fun (b c : bool) (ab : ~ (b /\ c)) => [eta introTF andP] ?Goal)
b, c:bool
ab:~ (b /\ c)

~ (b /\ c)
introTF : forall [P : Prop] [b c : bool], reflect P b -> (if c then P else ~ P) -> b = c introTF is not universe polymorphic Arguments introTF [P]%type_scope [b c]%bool_scope _ _ introTF is opaque Expands to: Constant Coq.ssr.ssrbool.introTF
b, c:bool
ab:~ (b /\ c)

~ (b /\ c)
done. Qed.

Let's look at some more machinery to work with specifiations for decision procedures. We are going to look at the eqn -- the decision procedure for equality on the nat type.

n, m:nat

reflect (n = m) (eqn n m)
n, m:nat

reflect (n = m) (eqn n m)

One way to prove this is to turn [reflect] into a bi-implication and prove the two directions by induction separately. An idiomatic way to do that is as follows:

n, m:nat

eqn n m -> n = m
n, m:nat
n = m -> eqn n m
iffP : forall [P Q : Prop] [b : bool], reflect P b -> (P -> Q) -> (Q -> P) -> reflect Q b iffP is not universe polymorphic Arguments iffP [P Q]%type_scope [b]%bool_scope _ (_ _)%function_scope iffP is opaque Expands to: Constant Coq.ssr.ssrbool.iffP
n, m:nat

eqn n m -> n = m
n, m:nat
n = m -> eqn n m

We need the trivial reflection view idP here to convert the boolean expression eqn n m to the proposition eqn n m = true (you don't see the = true part in the subgoals because of the is_true coercion).

The rest of the proof should be trivial at this point.

n, m:nat

eqn n m -> n = m
n, m:nat
n = m -> eqn n m
n, m:nat

n = m -> eqn n m
by move=> ->; elim: m. Qed.

Here is an example of using iffP with a non-idP argument. Here we use eqType -- a type with decidable equality and some machinery associated with it, like eqP.

T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T

reflect (y = x /\ 0 < n) (y \in nseq n x)
T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T

reflect (y = x /\ 0 < n) (y \in nseq n x)
T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T

reflect (y = x /\ 0 < n) ((0 < n) && (y == x))
T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T

reflect (y = x /\ 0 < n) ((y == x) && (0 < n))
T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T

y == x /\ 0 < n -> y = x /\ 0 < n
T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T
y = x /\ 0 < n -> y == x /\ 0 < n
T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T

y == x /\ 0 < n -> y = x /\ 0 < n
T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T
y = x /\ 0 < n -> y == x /\ 0 < n
T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T

y == x -> 0 < n -> y = x /\ 0 < n
T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T
y = x /\ 0 < n -> y == x /\ 0 < n
T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T

y = x -> 0 < n -> y = x /\ 0 < n
T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T
y = x /\ 0 < n -> y == x /\ 0 < n
eqP : forall {T : eqType}, Equality.axiom eq_op eqP is not universe polymorphic Expanded type for implicit arguments eqP : forall {T : eqType} {x y : T}, reflect (x = y) (x == y) Arguments eqP {T x y} eqP is opaque Expands to: Constant mathcomp.ssreflect.eqtype.eqP
T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T

y = x -> 0 < n -> y = x /\ 0 < n
T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T
y = x /\ 0 < n -> y == x /\ 0 < n
T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T

0 < n -> x = x /\ 0 < n
T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T
y = x /\ 0 < n -> y == x /\ 0 < n
T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T

y = x /\ 0 < n -> y == x /\ 0 < n
T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T

x == x /\ true
T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T

true /\ true
done.

A more idiomatic solution

T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T

reflect (y = x /\ 0 < n) (y \in nseq n x)
T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T

y = x -> 0 < n -> y = x /\ 0 < n
T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T
y == x -> 0 < n -> y == x /\ 0 < n

There is some code duplication here which can be reduced using -[ ] syntax:

T:eqType
n:nat
x, y:T

reflect (y = x /\ 0 < n) (y \in nseq n x)
by rewrite mem_nseq andbC; apply: (iffP andP)=> -[/eqP].

We cannot say just [/eqP] because Coq expects us to provide tactics for both subgoals and not just one. To bypass this restriction we use the - syntax.

Qed.

Rewriting with reflect predicates

One can rewrite with view lemmas if those represent equations, like maxn_idPl.

maxn_idPl : forall {m n : nat}, reflect (maxn m n = m) (n <= m) maxn_idPl is not universe polymorphic Arguments maxn_idPl {m n}%nat_scope maxn_idPl is opaque Expands to: Constant mathcomp.ssreflect.ssrnat.maxn_idPl

Let's see an example:

m, n1, n2:nat

(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat

(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n21:n2 <= n1

(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n12:n1 <= n2
(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
leq_total : forall m n : nat, (m <= n) || (n <= m) leq_total is not universe polymorphic Arguments leq_total (_ _)%nat_scope leq_total is opaque Expands to: Constant mathcomp.ssreflect.ssrnat.leq_total
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n21:n2 <= n1

(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n12:n1 <= n2
(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n21:n2 <= n1

(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n12:n1 <= n2
(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
minKn: forall m n : nat, maxn n (minn m n) = n
maxn_idPl: forall {m n : nat}, reflect (maxn m n = m) (n <= m)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n21:n2 <= n1

(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n12:n1 <= n2
(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n21:n2 <= n1

(m <= n1) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n12:n1 <= n2
(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)

Why does this trick work?

maxn_idPl le_n21 : maxn n1 n2 = n1
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n21:n2 <= n1

(m <= n1) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n12:n1 <= n2
(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)

OK, this is an ordinary equation, no wonder rewrite works. The view lemma [maxn_idPl] is not a function but behaves like one here. Let us check coercions!

m, n1, n2:nat
le_n21:is_true (n2 <= n1)

(m <= n1) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n12:is_true (n1 <= n2)
(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
elimT maxn_idPl le_n21 : maxn n1 n2 = n1
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n21:is_true (n2 <= n1)

(m <= n1) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n12:is_true (n1 <= n2)
(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)

No magic: elimT get implicitly inserted.

m, n1, n2:nat
le_n21:n2 <= n1

(m <= n1) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n12:n1 <= n2
(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
elimT : forall [P : Prop] [b : bool], reflect P b -> b -> P elimT is not universe polymorphic Arguments elimT [P]%type_scope [b]%bool_scope _ _ elimT is a coercion elimT is opaque Expands to: Constant Coq.ssr.ssrbool.elimT
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n21:n2 <= n1

(m <= n1) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n12:n1 <= n2
(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)

elimT is a coercion from reflect to Funclass, which means it gets inserted when one uses a view lemma as a function.

Essentially we invoke the following tactic:

m, n1, n2:nat
le_n21:n2 <= n1

(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n12:n1 <= n2
(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n21:n2 <= n1

(m <= n1) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n12:n1 <= n2
(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)

One can easily finish the proof, but let's simplify it first.

m, n1, n2:nat

(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)

We remove the symmetrical case first:

m, n1, n2:nat

(forall n1 n2 : nat, n2 <= n1 -> (m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)) -> (m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n21:n2 <= n1
(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat

(forall n1 n2 : nat, n2 <= n1 -> (m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)) -> (m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n21:n2 <= n1
(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n21:n2 <= n1

(m <= maxn n1 n2) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)
m, n1, n2:nat
le_n21:n2 <= n1

(m <= n1) = (m <= n1) || (m <= n2)

The rest is an exercise

Abort.

A specification example

allP : forall {T : eqType} {a : pred T} {s : seq T}, reflect {in s, forall x : T, a x} (all a s) allP is not universe polymorphic Arguments allP {T a} {s}%seq_scope allP is opaque Expands to: Constant mathcomp.ssreflect.seq.allP

Check out some other specs in the seq and ssrnat modules!

nilP: forall {T : Type} {s : seq T}, reflect (s = [::]) (nilp s)
all_filterP: forall {T : Type} {a : pred T} {s : seq T}, reflect ([seq x <- s | a x] = s) (all a s)
perm_nilP: forall {T : eqType} {s : seq T}, reflect (s = [::]) (perm_eq s [::])
natnseq0P: forall s : seq nat, reflect (s = nseq (size s) 0) (sumn s == 0)
permPl: forall {T : eqType} {s1 s2 : seq T}, reflect (perm_eql s1 s2) (perm_eq s1 s2)
permPr: forall {T : eqType} {s1 s2 : seq T}, reflect (perm_eq^~ s1 =1 perm_eq^~ s2) (perm_eq s1 s2)
all_nthP: forall {T : Type} {a : pred T} {s : seq T} (x0 : T), reflect (forall i : nat, i < size s -> a (nth x0 s i)) (all a s)
constantP: forall [T : eqType], T -> forall s : seq T, reflect (exists x : T, s = nseq (size s) x) (constant s)
all_pred1P: forall [T : eqType] (x : T) (s : seq T), reflect (s = nseq (size s) x) (all (pred1 x) s)
has_nthP: forall {T : Type} {a : pred T} {s : seq T} (x0 : T), reflect (exists2 i : nat, i < size s & a (nth x0 s i)) (has a s)
permP: forall {T : eqType} {s1 s2 : seq T}, reflect (count^~ s1 =1 count^~ s2) (perm_eq s1 s2)
allP: forall {T : eqType} {a : pred T} {s : seq T}, reflect {in s, forall x : T, a x} (all a s)
hasP: forall {T : eqType} {a : pred T} {s : seq T}, reflect (exists2 x : T, x \in s & a x) (has a s)
count_memPn: forall {T : eqType} {x : T} {s : seq T}, reflect (count_mem x s = 0) (x \notin s)
seq.nseqP: forall {T : eqType} {n : nat} {x y : T}, reflect (y = x /\ 0 < n) (y \in nseq n x)
subseqP: forall {T : eqType} {s1 s2 : seq T}, reflect (exists2 m : seq bool, size m = size s2 & s1 = mask m s2) (subseq s1 s2)
allPP: forall [T : eqType] [a : pred T] (s : seq T) [A : T -> Prop], (forall x : T, reflect (A x) (a x)) -> reflect {in s, forall x : T, A x} (all a s)
allPn: forall {T : eqType} {a : pred T} {s : seq T}, reflect (exists2 x : T, x \in s & ~~ a x) (~~ all a s)
hasPn: forall {T : eqType} {a : pred T} {s : seq T}, reflect {in s, forall x : T, ~~ a x} (~~ has a s)
subseq_uniqP: forall [T : eqType] [s1 s2 : seq T], uniq s2 -> reflect (s1 = [seq x <- s2 | mem s1 x]) (subseq s1 s2)
hasPP: forall [T : eqType] [a : pred T] (s : seq T) [A : T -> Prop], (forall x : T, reflect (A x) (a x)) -> reflect (exists2 x : T, x \in s & A x) (has a s)
nthP: forall {T : eqType} {s : seq T} {x : T} (x0 : T), reflect (exists2 i : nat, i < size s & nth x0 s i = x) (x \in s)
perm_consP: forall {T : eqType} {x : T} {s t : seq T}, reflect (exists (i : nat) (u : seq T), rot i t = x :: u /\ perm_eq u s) (perm_eq t (x :: s))
uniqPn: forall {T : eqType} (x0 : T) {s : seq T}, reflect (exists i j : nat, [/\ i < j, j < size s & nth x0 s i = nth x0 s j]) (~~ uniq s)
mapP: forall {T1 T2 : eqType} {f : T1 -> T2} {s : seq T1} {y : T2}, reflect (exists2 x : T1, x \in s & y = f x) (y \in [seq f i | i <- s])
uniqP: forall {T : eqType} (x0 : T) {s : seq T}, reflect {in gtn (size s) &, injective (nth x0 s)} (uniq s)
flattenP: forall {T : eqType} {A : seq (seq T)} {x : T}, reflect (exists2 s : seq_eqType T, s \in A & x \in s) (x \in flatten A)
perm_iotaP: forall {T : eqType} {s t : seq T} (x0 : T), let It := iota 0 (size t) in reflect (exists2 Is : seq nat_eqType, perm_eq Is It & s = [seq nth x0 t i | i <- Is]) (perm_eq s t)
leq_uniq_countP: forall [T : eqType] (x : T) [s1 : seq T] (s2 : seq T), uniq s1 -> reflect (x \in s1 -> x \in s2) (count_mem x s1 <= count_mem x s2)
allrelP: forall {T S : eqType} {r : T -> S -> bool} {xs : seq_predType T} {ys : seq_predType S}, reflect {in xs & ys, forall (x : T) (y : S), r x y} (allrel r xs ys)
flatten_mapP: forall {S T : eqType} {A : S -> seq T} {s : seq_predType S} {y : T}, reflect (exists2 x : S, x \in s & y \in A x) (y \in flatten [seq A i | i <- s])
all_allpairsP: forall {S : eqType} {T : S -> eqType} {R : Type} {p : pred R} {f : forall x : S, T x -> R} {s : seq S} {t : forall x : S, seq (T x)}, reflect (forall (x : S) (y : T x), x \in s -> y \in t x -> p (f x y)) (all p [seq f x y | x <- s, y <- t x])
allpairsPdep: forall {S : eqType} {T : S -> eqType} {R : eqType} {f : forall x : S, T x -> R} {s : seq S} {t : forall x : S, seq (T x)} {z : R}, reflect (exists (x : S) (y : T x), [/\ x \in s, y \in t x & z = f x y]) (z \in [seq f x y | x <- s, y <- t x])
allpairsP: forall {S T R : eqType} {f : S -> T -> R} {s : seq S} {t : seq T} {z : R}, reflect (exists p : S * T, [/\ p.1 \in s, p.2 \in t & z = f p.1 p.2]) (z \in [seq f x y | x <- s, y <- t])
leqif_refl: forall (m : nat) (C : bool), reflect (m <= m ?= iff C) C
leP: forall {m n : nat}, reflect (m <= n)%coq_nat (m <= n)
ltP: forall {m n : nat}, reflect (m < n)%coq_nat (m < n)
minn_idPr: forall {m n : nat}, reflect (minn m n = n) (n <= m)
minn_idPl: forall {m n : nat}, reflect (minn m n = m) (m <= n)
maxn_idPr: forall {m n : nat}, reflect (maxn m n = n) (m <= n)
maxn_idPl: forall {m n : nat}, reflect (maxn m n = m) (n <= m)
leqifP: forall (m n : nat) (C : bool), reflect (m <= n ?= iff C) (if C then m == n else m < n)

The inside syntax lets one look for lemmas inside a particular module only.

Specs as rewrite mutli-rules

We have seen reflect-predicates being able to rewrite boolean expressions corresponding to its index. We can take this approach even further. Let's see an example of a mutli-rule.

m, n:nat

m <= n <= m -> (m == n) || (n < m) || (m + n == 0)
m, n:nat

m <= n <= m -> (m == n) || (n < m) || (m + n == 0)
by case: ltngtP.

That was quick!

ltngtP : forall m n : nat, compare_nat m n (minn n m) (minn m n) (maxn n m) (maxn m n) (n == m) (m == n) (n <= m) (m <= n) (n < m) (m < n) ltngtP is not universe polymorphic Arguments ltngtP (_ _)%nat_scope ltngtP is opaque Expands to: Constant mathcomp.ssreflect.ssrnat.ltngtP
compare_nat : nat -> nat -> nat -> nat -> nat -> nat -> bool -> bool -> bool -> bool -> bool -> bool -> Set compare_nat is not universe polymorphic Arguments compare_nat (_ _ _ _ _ _)%nat_scope (_ _ _ _ _ _)%bool_scope Expands to: Inductive mathcomp.ssreflect.ssrnat.compare_nat
m, n:nat

m <= n <= m -> (m == n) || (n < m) || (m + n == 0)

case: ltngtP performs case analysis: it generates three subgoals corresponding to thee three cases, strictly less, equal, strictly greater.

m, n:nat

n < m -> false && true -> false || true || (m + n == 0)
m, n:nat
m < n -> true && false -> false || false || (m + n == 0)
m, n:nat
n = m -> true && true -> true || false || (m + n == 0)

Notice that a lot of boolean expressions got replaced with true or false depending on a concrete case we are covering. The ltngtP also works as a rewrite rule.

m, n:nat

n < m -> false && true -> false || true || (m + n == 0)
m, n:nat
m < n -> true && false -> false || false || (m + n == 0)
m, n:nat
n = m -> true && true -> true || false || (m + n == 0)
m, n:nat

m < n -> true && false -> false || false || (m + n == 0)
m, n:nat
n = m -> true && true -> true || false || (m + n == 0)
m, n:nat

m < n -> true && false -> false || false || (m + n == 0)
m, n:nat
n = m -> true && true -> true || false || (m + n == 0)
m, n:nat

n = m -> true && true -> true || false || (m + n == 0)
m, n:nat

n = m -> true -> true
done. Qed.

Let's see how one can implement this combined lemma.

Module Trichotomy.

First, we define a type family (indexed type) with indices corresponding to expressions we want to rewrite in subgoals. We use the Variant vernacular here which is exactly like Inductive but the type cannot refer to itself in its definition, in other words it's a non-recursive inductive type.

Variant compare_nat m n :
   bool -> bool -> bool -> bool -> bool -> bool -> Type :=
| CompareNatLt of m < n :
   compare_nat m n false false false true false true
| CompareNatGt of m > n :
   compare_nat m n false false true false true false
| CompareNatEq of m = n :
   compare_nat m n true true true true false false.

Next, we define a specification lemma which connect the type family above with concrete expressions we want to rewrite.

m, n:nat

compare_nat m n (n == m) (m == n) (n <= m) (m <= n) (n < m) (m < n)
m, n:nat

compare_nat m n (n == m) (m == n) (n <= m) (m <= n) (n < m) (m < n)
m, n:nat
nm:m < n

compare_nat m n (n == m) (n == m) false (m <= n) ((n != m) && false) ((n != m) && (m <= n))
m, n:nat
n <= m -> compare_nat m n (n == m) (n == m) true (m <= n) ((n != m) && true) ((n != m) && (m <= n))
m, n:nat
nm:m < n

compare_nat m n (n == m) (n == m) false (m <= n) ((n != m) && false) ((n != m) && (m <= n))
m, n:nat
n <= m -> compare_nat m n (n == m) (n == m) true (m <= n) ((n != m) && true) ((n != m) && (m <= n))
m, n:nat

n <= m -> compare_nat m n (n == m) (n == m) true (m <= n) ((n != m) && true) ((n != m) && (m <= n))
m, n:nat
lt_mn:n < m
eq_nm:true

compare_nat m n (n == m) (n == m) true false ((n != m) && true) ((n != m) && false)
m, n:nat
lt_mn:m <= n
eq_nm:n == m
compare_nat m n (n == m) (n == m) true true ((n != m) && true) ((n != m) && true)
m, n:nat
lt_mn:n < m
eq_nm:true

compare_nat m n (n == m) (n == m) true false ((n != m) && true) ((n != m) && false)
m, n:nat
lt_mn:m <= n
eq_nm:n == m
compare_nat m n (n == m) (n == m) true true ((n != m) && true) ((n != m) && true)
m, n:nat
lt_mn:m <= n
eq_nm:n == m

compare_nat m n (n == m) (n == m) true true ((n != m) && true) ((n != m) && true)
by rewrite eq_nm; constructor; apply/esym/eqP. Qed. End Trichotomy.

We can take this proof apart during a seminar but here are things to observe here:

  • The rewrite tactic support a language of patterns to focus rewriting on a particular part of the goal, e.g. in this case rewrite will only happen in a subterm corresponding to the _ == n pattern.
  • The ltnP spec lemma which is like ltngtP but simpler.
  • Just like one can do chained transformations of the top of the goal stack, one can do it for the conclusion: apply/esym/eqP.

Summary

Vernacular

  • Set Printing Coercions: turn on printing of implicit coercions -- very useful to better understand goals.
  • Search <pattern> inside <module>: narrow the scope of searching to a particular module.

Tactic/tactical summary

  • - action: can be used to connect unrelated views (move=> /V1 - /V2) or to force the interpretation of [] as case splitting when multiple subgoals are generated; -[/eqP].
  • case ident: term: case analyse on term and keep the corresponding equation in the context under the name of ident.
  • case: index_pattern / type_family: case analyse on a term of indexed type and perform substitutions of its indices according to index_pattern.
  • constructor: try to pick a data constructor automatically.
  • intuition: a solver for propositional intuitionistic logic.
  • without loss or wlog: "without loss of generality"-style reasoning.
  • apply/view_lemma: use the view mechanism on the conclusion of the goal. Can be chained together like apply/VL1/VL2/VL3.
  • rewrite tactic supports patterns: rewrite [<pattern>]<equation>.